- Because libraries must maintain a collection untainted by censorship, librarians may not delegate collection selection to others. See, e.g., Intellectual Freedom Committee (1999)
- According to at least one court, public librarians may not filter Internet access once they have decided to provide Internet access. See, Mainstream Louduon v. Board of Trustees of the Loudoun County Public Library, 24 F. Supp.2d 522 (E.D. Va 1998) The Loudoun decision now carries more weight since another court dismissed a complaint against a public library for refusing to filter Internet content. See, Kathleen R. v. City of LIvermore, Case No. V-015266-4 (Super. Ct.,Alameda Co.). T
Tuesday, February 19, 2008
Librarians As Censors
Has the Global Information Highway been derailed?
Many have predicted that the Internet would spread the ideals of democracy and intellectual freedom around the globe. After all, the Internet affords unprecedented access to information and provides ample opportunity for exchanging ideas via blogs and other communication mediums. But this has not yet happened. Instead, as tech visionaries work towards global on-line libraries, intellectual freedom has become an ever more challenging issue. Different countries define and value intellectual freedom differently—although some library associations overseas do share the ALA’s respect for intellectual freedom. See, IFLA for statements on intellectual freedom by libraries around the globe. And in many countries, including the U.S., privacy concerns may chill truly free exchanges of ideas over the Internet. As a result, the future health of intellectual freedom, and its existence in the age of the Internet, remains uncertain.
China is a prime example of a country that values intellectual freedom differently from the U.S., and certainly the ALA. While China has embraced the Internet as an information tool, it has also effectively quashed its people’s access to and use of politically unpopular material. (MacKinnon, 2007). p. 31. In fact, ‘“China operates the most extensive, technologically sophisticated, and broad-reaching system of Internet filtering in the world.”’ (MacKinnon, 2007) quoting (OpenNet Initiative 2005). p. 32. And when filters fail, China chills intellectual freedom through direct oppression and threats of reprisal. One example is Wang Xiaoning, a man who distributed information over the Internet in China. (Anonymous 2007, July). The distribution was supposedly anonymous, but, allegedly, Yahoo! HK gave Wang’s name to the police when asked about the postings—according to Wang, he was arrested, subjected to torture, and sentenced to ten years in prison. (Anonymous, 2007, July).
And China is not alone.
- Syria, Iran, Burma, and Vietnam are also considered “pervasive” filterers. (Fowler , 2008).
- In France, a new law could be applied so as to prevent people from posting violent images on the Internet. (Anonymous, 2007, May).
- Google has voluntarily mimicked Chinese censorship in its Chinese search engine. (Kreimer, 2006). p. 18.
- France has also sought to impose liability on Yahoo! for making Nazi paraphernalia available. (Kreimer, 2006). p. 19.
- Germany has imposed strict liability on Internet service providers (“ISPs”) that unwittingly host copyright infringement. (Kreimer, 2006). p. 20.
- ISPs must now filter whatever may be perceived as hate speech from French, German, and Swiss Internet users. (Kreimer, 2006). p. 20.
- Australia uses censors and regulators in tandem to find objectionable material and order the Internet provider to remove the content from the site. (Kreimer, 2006). p. 21.
“Internet censorship is growing, both in scale and sophistication.” (Haggerty, 2007, November). See also, OpenNet Initiative Maps. In reality, the Internet has become a tool by which governments can promote their own values and traditions, and not a method by which so-called free societies can open closed social systems to free discourse—assuming it is even proper for a country like the U.S. to impose its ideals on another country, like China. (Kreimer, 2006). p. 21. See also, (MacKinnon, 2007).
Still, why does it matter to us, and to intellectual freedom here at home, that China censors information on the web? It matters because, in our interconnected global world, many companies, including blog-hosts, are choosing to adjust their policies to accommodate the world’s most restrictive information systems. (Kreimer, 2006). p. 28. And by doing so, companies have restricted access to content in this country as well. (Kreimer, 2006). p. 28. It is costly to monitor and distinguish protected versus unprotected sanctionable speech, particularly when the ground rules change at each border. (Kreimer, 2006). Many intermediaries, when faced with the costs involved in keeping all nations happy, are likely to “abandon the effort to avoid errors and adopt a conscious policy of prophylactic self-censorship that blocks any content that could precipitate the threat of sanctions.” (Kreimer, 2006). P. 28. In effect, by corporate proxy, China or France or Germany, and so on, can curtail our intellectual freedom here in the United States.
This is not just speculation. In 2005, Microsoft’s Chinese edition of MSN Spaces blocked a variety of politically sensitive terms (sensitive in China that is) by first issuing a warning to the user, and then by blocking any suspect posting from user access in both China and the United States. It did so by removing each offending post directly from Microsoft’s U.S. servers. (MacKinnon, 2007). p. 41. After the public learned of Microsoft’s complicity with Chinese censors Microsoft changed its policy, somewhat—it now requires a written order from the censoring country and only blocks information from recipients in the censoring country. (MacKinnon, 2007). p. 41. But it appears likely that, absent public outrage, private for-profit companies in the information trade (particularly companies without Microsoft’s resources or public profile) will take the most economically viable path, and not the freest. (Kreimer, 2006). p. 28.
Although a U.S. user may ultimately be able to locate information equivalent to that which was censored elsewhere, how information is presented, by whom, and with what frequency all impact how users evaluate information and overall intellectual freedom in this country. Interfering with speech intermediaries is as detrimental to free speech as is silencing the speaker directly—and sometimes more so. (Kreimer, 2006). p. 17. A speaker faced with censorship might choose to self edit, or to initiate court action, but an intermediary will most likely choose to remove the offending material in its entirety. (Kreimer, 2006). p. 17.
Even worse, we cannot count on our own government to address foreign risks to intellectual freedom at home. Our government has also chosen to inhibit the free flow of electronic speech by pressuring information or speech intermediaries.
- As discussed by Anne, Internet service providers are expected to censor child pornography and filter content directed towards schools for obscenity and information harmful to minors.
- “In 1999, antiterrorism units of the FBI adopted a ‘good corporate citizenship program,’ which empowered them to seek to induce [Internet providers] to censor websites that were constitutionally protected but were not viewed by the FBI as consonant with the public interest.” (Kreimer, 2006). p. 24.
- As mentioned by Holly in our blog segment on the Patriot Act, federal authorities may unilaterally demand that intermediaries turn over communication records without informing the speaker. (Kreimer, 2006). p. 25.
- Our government has also sought to impose criminal liability on persons who assisted with designing Islamic websites. (Kreimer, 2006). p. 26.
Moreover, when intermediaries act as censor, instead of the government, there are no processes currently in place to ensure, for example, that the content removed from a website was really child pornography, and not an artist’s photo album. (Kreimer, 2006). p. 27-28. Because we all now rely on information intermediaries to learn and communicate with others, the intermediaries’ vulnerabilities have become everyone’s problem, including libraries.
Public Internet access in libraries has increased dramatically; a “1998 survey by the American Library Association[(“ALA”)] found that 73 percent of the nation's public libraries, including branches, now offer basic Internet access to their patrons.” (Corne-Revere, n.d.). For librarians, the prevalence of censorship in a medium on which libraries increasing rely raises a variety of ethical issues — issues that, if anyone’s interested, also happen to dovetail nicely with the ALA’s concerns on outsourcing. See, e.g., the ALA 1999 report, Outsourcing & Privatization in American Libraries. As a result, librarians today must question what their moral obligations or duties are in the context of both foreign and domestic Internet censorship.
The ALA has already defined what an ethical member of the professional should do in general terms. Article III and IV of the ALA’s Library Bill of Rights (which was discussed in detail in Yashmyn’s blog) read respectively that “[l]ibraries should challenge censorship in the fulfillment of their responsibility to provide information and enlightenment”; and “[l]ibraries should cooperate with all persons and groups concerned with resisting abridgment of free expression and free access to ideas.” And if one believes that Internet search tools and content are a form of outsourcing, or are analogous to it, ALA outsourcing reports make it clear that librarians cannot delegate content decisions to vendors and that contractual arrangements for outsourced services must ensure that patrons’ First Amendment rights are preserved. Intellectual Freedom Committee (1999).
The plain language of the first Library Bill of Rights assertion referred to above, and possibly the second, demands pro-activity. As do the ALA reports on outsourcing. Refraining from censorship personally is not enough; librarians must take steps to prevent censorship and privacy violations from occurring, at least within the library.
Therefore, in an age when censorship is occurring by proxy, beyond or outside the prohibitions of the First Amendment, on a service offered by U.S. libraries, but controlled by ISPs and other information intermediaries, the question becomes, must a librarian challenge corporate Internet censorship? As libraries go global and collaborate with other libraries around the world, must a librarian challenge censorship abroad? Under the terms of the Library Bill of Rights, is it ethical to participate in global Internet libraries and not challenge limitations placed on intellectual freedom by other governments? Is it enough to issue a statement through the ALA, or is more required to meet the librarian’s duty to challenge censorship? And, further, do librarians have an obligation to cooperate with political activists agitating for intellectual freedom in China? In Syria? And what does cooperation entail exactly?
Questions like these have been faced in the national arena, but acquire layers of complexity when looked at globally—not to mention the practical question of how effectively librarians in the U.S. can impact information policy in France, for example. Or whether it is realistic to expect librarians to cooperate in a meaningful manner with political dissidents fighting oppressive regimes overseas?
But in the end the stakes remain the same, whether the ethic of intellectual freedom can be meaningfully preserved in our country, as it participates more fully in the modern world.
Additional Questions:
- Do you feel that maintaining intellectual freedom on the Internet is essential for maintaining the vitality of intellectual freedom as an ideal?
- Do you feel it is possible to promote intellectual freedom on the Internet without first addressing conflicting cultural norms around the globe?
- If only some companies censor material in the U.S., does the fact that others are not censoring make the Internet free enough?
- Do librarians have an ethical obligation to research and use only those ISPs that avoid censorship?
Works cited:
ALA (Adopted June 18, 1948, amended February 2, 1961, June 28, 1967, and January 23, 1980). Library Bill of Rights. Retrieved on February 11, 2008, from http://www.ala.org/ala/oif/statementspols/statementsif/librarybillrights.htm.
Anonymous. (2007, July). Is it legal? Internet. Newsletter on Intellectual Freedom, 56(4), 168.
Anonymous. (2007, May). Paris, France. Dateline: foreign. Newsletter on Intellectual Freedom, 56(3), 125.
Corne-Revere, R. (n.d.). The First Amendment and the Media. Online Issues. Retrieved on February 11, 2008, from http://www.mediainstitute.org/ONLINE/FAM99/online_D.html.
Fowler, G.A. (2008, January 4). China tightens web-video rules; private operators brace for new censorship moves, but scope of effort unclear. Wallstreet Journal. (Eastern edition). New York, N.Y.
Haggerty, K. (2007, November). As states encroach on Internet governance around the world, IDRC is supporting a major new initiative that will investigate the impacts of Internet censorship in Asia. The International Research Development Centre. Retrieved on February 18, 2008, from http://www.idrc.ca/en/ev-116735-201-1-DO_TOPIC.html.
Intellectual Freedom Committee (1999). Response to the resolution in counsel document #24: Outsourcing and privatization in American libraries. Retrieved on February 11, 2008, from http://www.ala.org/ala/oif/iftoolkits/outsourcing/Default2446.htm.
Kreimer, S.F. (2006). Censorship by proxy: The first amendment, internet intermediaries, and the problem of the weakest link. University of Pennsylvania Law Review., 155(11), 12-101.
MacKinnon, R. (2008). Flatter world and thicker walls? Blogs, censorship and civic discourse in China. Public Choice, 134, 31-46.
Monday, February 18, 2008
Censorship in the Schools
- The internet is very tough to manage - as a professional she agrees with the freedom to read, but she also sees some benefit to filtering. It is a dilemma for her because protecting kids from something they are going to be using outside of school does not help them - it is more important to steer them to other sources. If a teacher accepts Wikipedia as a reference, then that is his/her prerogative. On the other hand, filters can be positive because they can prevent "unintended material" from reaching the student. Before filtering became more sophisticated, a student unintentionally received email from a porn site. In another situation, education web sites were being "porn-napped" by advertisers who provided disguised links to their pornographic sites on these seemingly safe web sites at school.
- "Good stuff is not free on the internet." If students want to use Wikipedia and Google, then, according to Karen, we must teach them to evaluate the sites they go to. If unreliable information is used then the student suffers. Since Wikipedia has been banned, Karen has seen some positive changes in the students research habits - they are not using Google as much nor wasting so much time as people do when they get distracted by the myriad of unrelated information on Wikipedia. The students are recognizing that their time is valuable and appreciating qualified references that the school provides and pays for.
- On a positive note for Wikipedia, it can provide a jumping off point for research about a subject that there is not much information about with keywords and related subjects.
Saturday, February 16, 2008
How Right is the Bill of Rights (along with all of its interpretations)?
In the Bill of Rights, the American Library Association (the “ALA”) states that libraries are forums for information and ideas and provides basic policies to guide library services. The Bill of Rights is one of several ALA-related documents intended to assure the library patron of intellectual freedom in his use of library services.
The ALA cannot mandate that libraries adopt the Bill of Rights, but many libraries do in any case. As intended, they use it to form the philosophical basis of their collections development policy.
Research in Michigan has shown that in high school libraries, when a statement of philosophy such as the Bill of Rights is included in materials selection policies, it is less likely that a challenge will result in actual removal of a book from the shelf. (Hopkins, 1996). p. 3 of 11. But one observer notes that even if librarians obediently incorporate the Bill of Rights into their collection development polices, authors of textbooks on collections development largely ignore it, for its lack of consistent practical guidance, as will be discussed below. (Hitchcock, 2005) pp. 5-7.
Two Specific Library Reactions to the Bill of Rights. And if not all public libraries pay close attention to the Bill of Rights—to either affirm their respect for it or to reject it—at least some certainly do. In 1995, the Loudoun County (Virginia) Library Board, with several recently elected deeply conservative members, voted to delete statements in the Bill of Rights] dealing with censorship and substitute weaker language in their place. (Parr, 1995) p. 6. But after protests from patrons, the Board did not entirely gut the policy. Further, since that time, with the replacement of those members with other members, the library has readopted its previous ALA-version of the Bill of Rights.
And ten years later, in 2005, the Johnson County (Kansas) Library Board removed the Bill of Rights from its own materials-collection policy. One member had earlier been quoted as saying that “if you have to have all points of view, you’re saying we need to have information on acts of terrorism.” (Kansas board deselects Library Bill of Rights, 2005). However, one month later—after intense public criticism and the selection of new board members—this Bill of Rights was also reinstated. (Johnson County reaffirms Library Bill of Rights, 2005).
Some Specific Criticisms. So libraries, library boards, library users, and observers are paying attention to the Bill of Rights. But they’re not all agreeing on the quality of its content. It has received significant criticism, ranging from the unconditioned extreme of its interpretation of “intellectual freedom”--for instance, the fact that the Bill of Rights encourages giving children the exact same access to information that adults have (under Article IV) also rankles many observers. And the criticism extends to the quality of the drafting of the Bill of Rights. Articles II and III are the subjects of the discussion below.
Article II focuses on the materials themselves and the library’s responsibility to include materials covering every point of view on an issue. It also prohibits their removal based on partisan or doctrinal—or as has sometimes been interpreted as “political” disapproval.
Article III requires that libraries take a proactive stance against any form of censorship.
Article II.
“Sound factual authority.” From 1948 to 1967, Article II applied to books or other reading matter of “sound factual authority.” But in the early 60s, a Catholic librarian in Peoria, Illinois, excluded a Protestant text because, he said, it lacked “sound factual authority.” In response, in 1967, this condition was removed from Article II.
But was this the appropriate action? Does it mean that if a library is offered a donation of The Encyclopedia of Mushrooms (Dickinson & Lucas, 1979)—which contained erroneous information about the edibility of a mushroom and which resulted in several people becoming so ill that they needed liver transplants—that the library must accept it? (Baldwin, Summer 1996).
Labelling. As mentioned in yesterday’s blog, the ALA is cautious of labeling—calling it a potential form of censorship. One of the interpretations is devoted to this concept. The ALA supports it only when it can serve as a “viewpoint-neutral directional [aid]” to save the library patron time. But one important justification for it besides the one described by the ALA might be that the freedom to read or view what one wants is meaningful only when one can know what it is that one is about to read or view. (Fricke, 2000) p. 474.
“…Presenting all points of view.” This clause in the first sentence seems to be taken literally by nobody. Even the library with the largest budget certainly couldn’t expect to take the effort to try to locate and obtain every such book. (Doyle, 2002).
Article III.
Inappropriate-to-distribute information. One set of authors points out that—contrary to what the Bill of Rights and its interpretations suggest—there are at least some instances in which content-based censorship would be recommended. These include instances in which intellectual property rights are otherwise violated; where the information that is being provided invades privacy (for instance contains genetic information about individuals). They also point out that medical information resulting from experiments at concentration camps in Nazi Germany, provides “information and enlightenment” as stated in Article III. (Fricke, 2000) pp. 476-7.
So wouldn’t the librarian want to censor provision of this information? Aren’t these therefore clear reasons why Article III isn’t desirable in its current form?
Democratic-principle approach. Another observer looks at the issue more from the perspective of democratic principles. First he notes that most people favor some kind of content-based censorship. Then he points out that in the librarian profession, intellectual freedom is far more broad than the ordinary First-Amendment conception of free speech. He then concludes that “the idea that a publicly funded [state] institution has a duty to advance a conception of free speech in clear tension with ordinary views and well-established constitutional law is difficult to reconcile with commonly accepted principles of democracy.” (Himma, 2004) pp. 2-3 of 3. Does this not seem like another reason that Article III should be reconsidered?
Some legal context. The case (Board of Education v. Pico, 1982) that the Supreme Court has decided regarding librarian collections policies has not resulted in any clear black-and-white law. After a school library’s books had been challenged, the school board appointed a review committee, which recommended returning five of the books to the shelves, placing two on restricted shelves, and removing two of them. The board instead decided to remove all but one of the books, calling them “anti-American, anti-Christian, anti-Semitic, and just plain filthy.” (Notable First Amendment court cases; Baldwin, Summer 1996) The Supreme Court recognized the discretion of a school library to determine the content of a public school library, but stated that it may not remove books “simply because they dislike the ideas contained” in them. And they could not “…seek by their removal to prescribe what shall be orthodox in politics, nationalism, religion, or other matters of opinion.” A trial was ordered to determine just what the school board’s motivations had been. (Only the rationale for requiring the trial was not agreed to by a clear majority of the 9-member Supreme Court, and it’s not known what today’s Supreme Court would decide on this issue.) But the trial didn’t happen. The case had gone on for years, and neither party pursued the case. (Baldwin, Summer 1996; Notable First Amendment court cases).
The outcome of this trial could have shed some interesting light on just how close to—or far from—common law the actual Bill of Rights sits.
Loudoun County, mentioned earlier in this posting, is also the site of the Internet filtering that led to a lawsuit brought against the library on the grounds that (i.) the filtering applied to not just chidren’s use, but adult usage as well and (ii) the filtering software was overly broad, excluding non-offending sites. In 1998, the judge—who was also trained as a librarian, the current Director of Libraries tells me—held that the overinclusiveness of the software and its use on adults as well as children, made its use unconstitutional. (Notable First Amendment court cases).
While courts condemn censorship, they still recognize a right of educators to “inculcate social values.” But the Bill of Rights simply does not. (Baldwin, 2006). So does this mean that if the Loudoun software had applied only to children and had been able to better censor sites, that the library could have continued to use it? Should the library have been able to continue to use it?
Responses. Defenders of the Bill of Rights suggest not throwing out the baby with the bath water. That is, clearly the concept of intellectual freedom deserves and needs to be expressed in some document, whether or not one agrees to the broad form of it that the ALA advocates (extending to children of all ages). Doyle (July 2002). Even some scholars who critique the Bill of Rights recognize this and suggest rewriting the Bill of Rights as two documents. The first would be one that clearly states what the library patron’s rights are, particularly under First Amendment law. That is, the ALA should generate a document that states what actual U.S. law permits the user to expect from his library. But also, there would be a complementing document—something like the ALA Code of Ethics—that describes the aspirational goals of the ALA. This is where the ALA would exhibit its support for intellectual freedom in its fully unconditional form. (Wiegand, Summer 1996) At least one author—Hitchcock—has proposed a revision to Article II (at 15 or so lines long, it was too long to include in this posting, but it is included in his article, the citation for which appears below).
So can libraries that disagree with the Bill of Rights (on substance) just ignore it and implement the policies that they think are best for their communities? Should they? How about those who disagree with the Bill of Rights based on wording alone?
Does it seem to you that your local library is doing a good job of adhering to its own Bill of Rights (if it has adopted one)? Do the librarians even know what it says?
How important is the Bill of Rights to you actually?
Works Cited
Baldwin, G. B. (Summer 1996). The Library Bill of Rights - a critique - The Library Bill of Rights [Electronic Version]. Library Trends, 45. Retrieved January 20, 2008, from http://findarticles.com/p/articles/mi_m1387/is_n1_v45/ai_18616657
Doyle, T. (July 2002). A critical discussion of "The ethical presuppositions behind the Library Bill of Rights" [Electronic Version]. The Library Quarterly, 72, 275-293. Retrieved February 9, 2008, from http://proquest.umi.com.proxy.lib.wayne.edu
Fricke, M., Kay Mathiesen, and Don Fallis. (October 2000). The ethical presuppositions behind the Library Bill of Rights. Library Quarterly, 70(4), 468-491.
Himma, K. E. (July 2004). Libraries as political advocates: A critique of the Library Bill of Rights, Article III [Electronic Version]. Alki, 20, 21-23. Retrieved February 9, 2008, from http://vnweb.hwwilsonweb.com.proxy.lib.wayne.edu
Hitchcock, L. A. (2005). An examination of Article Two of the Library Bill of Rights. Public Library Quarterly, 24(2), 1-18.
Hopkins, D. M. (Summer 1996). The Library Bill of Rights and school library media programs - includes related information on Library Bill of Rights and its interpretations - the Library Bill of Rights [Electronic Version]. Library Trends, 45. Retrieved January 27, 2008, from http://findarticles.com/p/articles/mi_m1387/is_n1_v45/ai_18616660
Johnson County reaffirms Library Bill of Rights [Electronic. (May 20, 2005). Version]. American Libraries. Retrieved February 14, 2008, from http://www.ala.org/ala/alonline/currentnews/newsarchive/2005abc/may2005ab/johnsonco.cfm
Kansas board deselects Library Bill of Rights. (April 29, 2005). [Electronic. (May 20, 2005). Version]. American Libraries. Retrieved February 14, 2008, from http://www.ala.org/ala/alonline/currentnews/newsarchive/2005abc/april2005ab/kansasbillrights.cfm
Notable First Amendment court cases. Retrieved February 3, 2008, from http://www.ala.org/ala/oif/firstamendment/courtcases/courtcases.htm
Parr, C. S. (July-September, 1995). The Library Bill of Rights in Loudoun County. Virginia Librarian, 6-8.
Wiegand, S. A. (Summer 1996). Reality bites: the collision of rhetoric, rights, and reality and the Library Bill of Rights - includes related information on American Library Association's Code of Ethics - The Library Bill of Rights [Electronic Version]. Library Trends, 45. Retrieved January 20, 2008, from http://findarticles.com/p/articles/mi_m1387/is_n1_v45/ai_18616661
Friday, February 15, 2008
An Introduction to the Intellectual Freedom Blog
Librarians call it “intellectual freedom.” And intellectual freedom is the concept that “accords to all library users the right to seek and receive information on all subjects from all points of view without having the subject of one’s interest examined or scrutinized by others.” [emphasis in original] (Intellectual Freedom Manual, 2006) p. 3.
If the values expressed in that definition look familiar, it’s because they share the same philosophical underpinnings as the First Amendment. The thought is that if there’s a right to free speech, there must be a corollary right to free access to speech—in all its forms. As will be discussed in a subsequent blog this week, there has been debate on whether intellectual freedom should have some limits. (After all, freedom of speech has limits—for example, “fighting words” are not protected by the First Amendment, nor is child pornography, nor libel or defamation, nor “obscenity,” etc.) And that debate continues. But from it, more detail on the value of intellectual freedom has been garnered.
Specifically, as the American Library Association (the “ALA”) points out: “Intellectual freedom is the basis for our democratic system. We expect our people to be self-governors. But to do so responsibly, our citizenry must be well-informed. Libraries provide the ideas and information, in a variety of formats, to allow people to inform themselves.” ("Intellectual Freedom and Censorship Q & A," 2007) And it applies to children, too. The thought is that they need to cultivate critical skills needed to distinguish good ideas from bad by the time they come of age and become a part of the political process. (Doyle, July 2002) p. 7 of 15.
Further, free speech (and access to it) is important because it encourages a battle among ideas in which the best ideas survive, to everyone’s benefit; and even the most widely accepted ideas are subjected to opposing viewpoints in order to continue to test their validity—again, to everyone’s benefit. (Fricke, 2000) p. 474.
It is hard to argue with the above points. (Or is it?) But how exactly do they relate to a 12-year-old girl who wants to check out pornographic material—not child porn—but porn nonetheless? Under the notion of intellectual freedom, she should be allowed to take such material. But how exactly does this contribute to the world of ideas to which she is exposed?
Censorship infringes the autonomy and freedom of the individual person, preventing him from being able to make up his own mind on what to read or see. (Fricke, 2000) p. 474.
The ALA is the professional association that establishes guidelines and policies that all libraries are encouraged to follow. The ALA is a particularly prolific association, having generated a large number of policies and other statements. In its statements—which include among others, Libraries: An American Value statement (adopted Feb. 3, 1999); the Freedom to Read Statement (adopted in 1953 (during McCarthyism) and last amended June 30, 2004); the Freedom to View Statement (endorsed Jan. 10, 1990); the Code of Ethics of the American Library Association (adopted June 28, 1997 and amended Jan. 22, 2008); and, most famously, the Library Bill of Rights (adopted June 18, 1948, last amended Jan. 23, 1980, and inclusion of “age” reaffirmed Jan. 24, 1996) and its numerous associated interpretations—the ALA is consistent in opposing any restrictions on intellectual freedom.
For instance, with respect to labels and ratings systems, ALA is cautious about the former and opposed to the latter. (ALA believes that even though labels can be “viewpoint-neutral directional aids that save the time of users,” they might also be used as “attempts to prejudice or discourage users or restrict their access to materials.”) (Intellectual Freedom Manual, 2006) p. 171.
Even though historically there had been a tradition of libraries “guarding” their patrons from materials that weren’t deemed fit to be read, by the 1950s at latest, librarians—or at least the ALA—had begun to express rejection of paternalism (or being a parent by proxy). Libraries that adhere to ALA’s policies now simply do not censor. Period. But not all libraries, of course, adhere to ALA’s extremist (some might say) policies.
The issue of ethics plays a large role in this area. First, ALA asserts that it is naturally the role of the library to enforce intellectual freedom, because only in the library can self-directed learning, with no outside-imposed limits, take place. With that said, ALA’s Code of Ethics states that “[e]thical dilemmas occur when values are in conflict. The American Library Association Code of Ethics states the values to which we are committed, and embodies the ethical responsibilities of the profession in this changing information environment.” ("Code of Ethics of the American Library Association," 2008)
But professional ethics aren’t the only kind that may affect a library’s responsibilities to its patrons. As one set of authors quoted, with minors in mind: ‘[n]or must we deprive [children] of the nurture, the helping hand, the guidance, the tools for seeking truth and knowing when it is discovered. We cannot simply turn them loose in our jaded information society without helping them understand that some of the information is false, is evil, is dangerous, is misleading, or is ambiguous…That may not be a legal obligation but it is clearly a moral duty for every librarian, every teacher, every parent and person in a free society.” (Fricke, 2000) pp. 485-6.
Is it true that libraries have no role other than the one articulated in the ALA documents—that is, to promote an atmosphere of intellectual freedom for the patron?
Children have access to far more “dangerous” materials now—particularly via the Internet—than they did in years past. Is this by itself reason for libraries to exercise caution in the materials that it makes accessible to children?
Numerous issues are being debated within the area of intellectual freedom. Below are the topics that we will be discussing throughout the coming week.
1. How Right is the Bill of Rights (along with all of its interpretations)? Attempts at censorship by individuals and organizations alike continue, and laws are passed (even if held unconstitutional) that attempt to restrict what children in particular may be exposed to. In this environment, the most called-upon ALA document to assert the ideal of intellectual freedom is—according to some observers—unrealistic in its virtually unconditional rejection of any form of censorship. Yashmyn will explore some of these claims and some responses made by Bill of Rights defenders.
2. Intellectual Freedom, Librarians, and the PATRIOT Act will explore the threat posed to the ideals of the information profession in regards to the passage of the PATRIOT ACT. Librarians and the patrons they serve are now subject to an unprecedented level of surveillance by the government. Holly will explore the librarian’s ethical responsibilities and objections to this infringement on intellectual freedom.
3. Censorship in the Schools will look at a specific case of school censorship in Grosse Pointe, Michigan, exploring the variables that affect what school libraries allow in relation to use of the Internet by students. Anne will explore how the problem can arise, who is in charge of addressing the situation, and how the situation is handled—as well as ask whether the outcome can be of benefit to the students, or whether their intellectual freedom is simply being repressed.
4. In the modern world, many people rely on the Internet to communicate with one another and to retrieve information. Libraries provide the public with access to the Internet, and must, therefore, consider issues that affect the Internet service they provide. In Has the Global Information Highway been Derailed? Kathryn will discuss how differing visions of intellectual freedom around the globe have caused Internet service providers to censor content both at home and abroad. As a result, American libraries today are, in effect, providing services that do not always respect or preserve intellectual freedom, an ideal that librarians are expected to protect and promote. This blog will conclude by exploring what the role of the librarian should be on this issue.
5. As Lester Asheim noted in his seminal 1953 essay “Not Censorship But Selection” (found at the ALA Web site), the librarian must be on guard against becoming a censor herself. Over fifty years later, in The Librarian as Censor, we examine the factors that must be carefully considered by the librarian before he may assert, “But I’m not censoring (nor am I simply passing the buck to someone else to act as censor).”
6. And on the last day, we’ll highlight the trends in the responses that the posted questions evoke.
Works Cited
Code of Ethics of the American Library Association. (2008, February 13, 2008). from http://www.ala.org/ala/oif/statementspols/codeofethics/codeethics.htm
Doyle, T. (July 2002). A critical discussion of "The ethical presuppositions behind the Library Bill of Rights" [Electronic Version]. The Library Quarterly, 72, 275-293. Retrieved February 9, 2008, from http://proquest.umi.com.proxy.lib.wayne.edu
Fricke, M., Kay Mathiesen, and Don Fallis. (2000). The ethical presuppositions behind the Library Bill of Rights. Library Quarterly, 70(4), 468-491.
Intellectual Freedom and Censorship Q & A. (2007). Retrieved January 20, 2008, from http://www.ala.org/ala/oif/basics/intellectual.htm
Intellectual Freedom Manual (7th ed.). (2006). Chicago: Office for Intellectual Freedom, American Library Association.
Scales, P. (September 2007). Ain't that a shame. School Library Journal, 53(9), 30.
Thursday, February 7, 2008
Monday, February 4, 2008
Friday, February 1, 2008
THANKS! GOOD JOB GROUP ONE
"Library Garden" blog - discussion about different types of libraries
Xanthe Muller